Tuesday, September 23, 2014

Arendt, Heidegger and Eichmann

In a recent book on the Eichmann papers, by Stangneth (Eichmann Before Jerusalem: The Unexamined Life of a Mass Murderer)[1], the author presents a superbly researched and prepared documentation on Eichmann and his thought as well as his putative strategy when dealing with the Israeli Courts at his Trial. This book also peripherally reflects on the Arendt book of over a half a century ago at the time of the Trial which caused such uproar. In the Trial, Arendt had asked to be sent and record what transpired. This was in the early sixties and at the time she was in New York. Her reporting became an amalgam of her German scholarship, of which Heidegger was central, and in an almost equal way her place in the then New York intellectual circles. Both influences became filters for what she saw and how she then reported the events at the Trial.

Benhabib in the NY Times has written a critique of the book and she states[2]:

The Emory University historian Deborah E. Lipstadt told The Times this month that Stangneth “shatters” Arendt’s portrait of Eichmann. In The Jewish Review of Books, the intellectual historian Richard Wolin writes: “Arendt had her own intellectual agenda, and perhaps out of her misplaced loyalty to her former mentor and lover, Martin Heidegger, insisted on applying the Freiburg philosopher’s concept of ‘thoughtlessness’ (Gedankenlosigkeit) to Eichmann. In doing so, she drastically underestimated the fanatical conviction that infused his actions.”

The fact is that Arendt had an affair with Heidegger when she was his student, as one gathers he had affairs with other students at the same period, all the while he was married. Arendt continued a somewhat close relationship with Heidegger up to her death despite the fact that Heidegger was a member of the Nazi party and had personally expelled Jews from his Faculty. Heidegger had a long history of extreme National Socialist tendencies and his joining the Nazi Party was but a step in that process[3].

This was a complex relationship as exhibited by the book by Ettinger which recounts the letters exchanged between Heidegger and Arendt. Ettinger’s work allows insight into the complex and continuing relationship between Arendt and Heidegger, a relationship built in many ways by the basics of German philosophy, from Kant onwards. She remains almost devoted to him to the end, despite the continual exposure of his actions during the War and before. Heidegger in a manner that we see in Eichmann tries to reconstruct a new portrayal of his actions, trying to show that he was not a real Nazi and that his actions were just in line with what was expected of him at the time. It is this situational ethics that somehow Arendt dismisses and she renews and expands the friendship despite the involvement that Heidegger had.

Benhabib continues:

This sort of dismissal of Arendt’s work — essentially a rejection of the “banality of evil” argument — is by no means new, but it does not hold up when one truly understands the meaning of her phrase. Couldn’t Eichmann have been a fanatical Nazi and banal? What precisely did Arendt mean then when she wrote that Eichmann “was not stupid. It was sheer thoughtlessness — something by no means identical with stupidity — that predisposed him to become one of the greatest criminals of that period.”? Arendt certainly did not think that ordinary human beings were all potential Eichmanns; nor did she diminish the crime Eichmann committed against the Jewish people. In fact, she accused him of “crimes against humanity,” and approved his death sentence, with which many, including the Jewish philosopher Martin Buber, disagreed.

The problem with this argument is that Arendt examined Eichmann by what he said at Trial, and she did not examine the record of Eichmann as one would have done either as a Historian or as the Prosecutor. Eichmann, the defendant, had prepared himself for the very role of Defendant. His writings as presented by Stangneth clearly demonstrate the mind of a Nazi, clever, plotting, planning and executing with precision. His defense at Trial was a planned and rehearsed presentation of what he wanted people to believe. Arendt it appears fell into the trap. The four walls of her understanding of Eichmann were delimited by the well prepared presentation he made at Trial. In contrast, in Stangneth, we see the drafts of Eichmann’s own words and what is revealed is the truth of what Eichmann truly was, a classic Nazi.

Thus the Benhabib defense of Arendt is somewhat weak. Arendt, it appears, went to the Trial to absorb from the Eichmann testimony a measure of the man. Yet as was shown in his writings and with an additional half century of discovery the man was quite complex and had anticipated such an event as the Trial. Thus he took it upon himself to present a stage persona at the Trial as a means of presenting his message.

To better understand the mindset of Arendt at the time of the Trial one need read Elizabetta Ettinger work on the correspondence between Heidegger and Arendt[4]. Ettinger had access to the papers, via allegedly Mary McCarthy, a close friend of Arendt, and a fellow traveler in the circle of the then New York intellectual elite. As Wistrich stated in Commentary on the review of Ettinger[5]:

Among the story’s more troubling aspects is the extent of Arendt’s submissiveness to Heidegger. Both as a student and later as a friend and equal she displayed an extraordinary readiness to put herself at his beck and call, to place him on a pedestal, and to subject herself to his arrogance. Ettinger, whose analysis eschews crude psychological reductionism, accounts for Arendt’s actions in broad sociological and historical terms:

[Arendt] shared the insecurity of many assimilated Jews who were still uncertain about their place, still harboring deep doubts about themselves. By choosing her as his beloved, Heidegger fulfilled for Hannah the dream of generations of German Jews, going back to such pioneers of assimilation as Rahel Varnhagen.

The irony here is that Arendt’s own book-length study of Rahel Varnhagen, a German Jewess prominent in early-19th-century literary circles, displays keen insight into the delusions and self-deceptions which are entailed in the Varnhagen “model” of assimilation, but which in her relationship with Heidegger she appeared unable to resist.

The assimilation construct was one of trying to shed the long held anti-Semitism on the part of the non-Jewish population. Arendt it appears tried to shed that both with her relationship with Heidegger and possibly by her later claim of certain German Jews facilitating the work of the Nazis, a claim rejected by many.

Benhabib further states:

It is this strange mixture of bravado and cruelty, of patriotic idealism and the shallowness of racialist thinking that Arendt sensed because she was so well attuned to Eichmann’s misuse of the German language and to his idiosyncratic deployment of concepts like the Categorical Imperative. As Stangneth puts it, “Hannah Arendt, whose linguistic and conceptual sensibilities had been honed on classical German literature, wrote that Eichmann’s language was a roller coaster of thoughtless horror, cynicism, whining self-pity, unintentional comedy and incredible human wretchedness.” Eichmann’s self-immunizing mixture of anti-Semitic clichés, his antiquated idiom of German patriotism and the craving for the warrior’s honor and dignity, led Arendt to conclude that Eichmann could not “think” — not because he was incapable of rational intelligence but because he could not think for himself beyond clichés. He was banal precisely because he was a fanatical anti-Semite, not despite it.

Eichmann had studied Jewish culture and thought, almost as a way to perfect his job. Thus he knew his adversary, his prey, oftentimes using that knowledge to effect his task. Arendt in many ways was critiquing Eichmann for his lack of acumen, lack of education, and then and again Eichmann had spent years developing this very persona as a means to present his tale, and most likely Arendt fell into the well laid trap. One could truly question the use of the phrase “banal” for Eichmann, for he was a shrewd manipulator of not only the facts but oftentimes of the audience listening to them.

In contrast in a review in the NY Times by Schuessler the author states[6]:

Listening to Eichmann in Jerusalem, Arendt saw an “inability to think.” Listening to Eichmann before Jerusalem, Ms. Stangneth sees a master manipulator skilled at turning reason, that weapon of the enemy, against itself.

That assessment is true but it appears to be only part of the overall truth. On the one hand Arendt did not due her due diligence; she did not independently investigate Eichmann. On the other had she let her Heideggerian training overtake the cunning rationality of Eichmann, she failed to see him as an actor in a play reading lines he had rehearsed again and again. One could say she let her German arrogance get in the way of what was in front of her, true evil. She was still a student of Heidegger, she was not able to become a common Police detective and see a criminal for what he was.

As Honan stated in the NY Times in a review of Ettinger in 1995[7]:

Heidegger, then the newly appointed rector of Albert-Ludwigs-University in Freiburg, had just joined the Nazi party and had delivered the infamous rector's address in which he declared his allegiance to Hitler. With heavy sarcasm, he denied Arendt's accusations. The truth is, as Professor Ettinger points out. His anti-Semitism had been well-established four years previously when he wrote to warn a high official in the Ministry of Education against the "growing Judiaization" of Germany's "spiritual life." Among his more abominable acts while rector in Freiburg, Heidegger banned from the campus all Jewish professors including his mentor, the aging Edmund Husserl —an act that is believed to have contributed to Husserl's death.

In a sense, as Arendt accused many German Jews of complicity with the Nazis out of some form of self-deception, perhaps she also could be criticized for missing the point of Eichmann by a form of self-interpretation. Eichmann may very well have used his well-planned defense as a means of leaving a trail of confusion to all but those who would eventually become privy to his writings.

To understand the conflicts of Arendt one may look for the inherent conflicts in Heidegger; his philosophy and his life. To do so it is worth examining the book by Winograd and Flores written in the 1980s[8]. Winograd was well known and highly respected at MIT at the time as a brilliant engineer in the Artificial Intelligence community. His career has subsequently secured that reputation. Flores was a politician in exile from Chile, a former member of the prior Communist Government overthrown by Pinochet, studying Philosophy at Berkeley. The combination of these two individuals had created a book, which now some 26 years later, is truly timeless.

The book fundamentally is a fusion of philosophy with technology and it does so through the eyes and minds of philosophers, especially Heidegger. By doing so, the authors demonstrate what technology, media, can do to not only elucidate knowledge but to frame and reposition what we seem to feel is “immutable truth”. Truth then becomes what we may perceive through the eyes of the medium, the signs placed before us so to speak. Thus, as we see so many “Apps” being developed on so many platforms in today’s world we seem not to stop and ask the question of how these Apps may be changing what we hold as knowledge, as truth, and how they reflect on the meaning of our existence. The authors have used this work to address these issues in the context of Heidegger and his view of being. Thus one can use this interpretation of Heidegger as a lens to focus on the relationship between the view of Arendt of Eichmann’s world. In a sense, Eichmann used the medium of the Trial as a way to recast Truth, and it was incumbent upon Arendt, having been trained by Heidegger, to recognize this. She did not.

The authors use the ideas of such opaque philosophers as Heidegger to establish a basis for their exposition. As Scrunton has noted Heidegger is obtuse, he is a quintessential German, creating a plethora of neologisms in German, which get half translated to English[9]. Heidegger deals with existence, ontology, and how we as humans are created as individuals by our interactions. The example of a man using a hammer to insert a nail becomes the amalgam of the hammer, human and nails as a process, and it is that at hand process that the human understands and becomes one with hammering. In a sense that is what we do when we create programs; we try to engage the human user with the process and its externalities to become one concerted effort.

Chapter 3 is seminal, for it is a wonderful summation of Heidegger and Gadamer, or what they would have said had they tried to do it in a few pages. The rationalist versus the idealist, the subject and object, the observed and the observer are all explored, The introduction of Heidegger’s Dasein is made in such a manner that the reader just flows with its insertion as being-in-the-world, and that one comes away with a highly readable and understandable grasp of what Heidegger meant to say[10].

They end with, “Heidegger insists that it is meaningless to talk about the existence of objects and their properties in the absence of concernful activity, with its potential for breaking down”. The interaction between the individual and the medium presenting facts then is essential to understanding. It is akin to the McLuhan statement regarding any medium used for transmitting knowledge, that is the medium will define what is truth or knowledge, not the “facts” or objects which the one conveying them wishes to transfer. This understanding or interaction of message and messenger, the hermeneutic view, and object and understanding, were what the authors saw as critical in developing “software”.

Now here we again come to Eichmann. Eichmann was in a sense both the messenger and the message. He viscerally understood that and had prepared for the confrontation that was his Trial. Heidegger understood that, it was Dasein confronting the world. The one wonders why Arendt of all people would not have had the openness to both understand that as well as the ability to translate it properly.

Breakdown can be a noun or a verb. As a noun it is failure, as a verb it is “taking apart”. [11] For Heidegger it was the noun that was operative. It was a failure of something. In essence we “learn by our mistakes”. Ironically Heidegger did not achieve this and Arendt was a front row observer of that process. As Koschmann et al state:

Heidegger, Leont'ev, and Dewey held surprisingly similar views on the role of breakdown or failure as a means of revealing the nature of the world around us. For Heidegger, the resources by which we conduct our day-to-day activities do not usually require our conscious awareness. If our ongoing activity is blocked, however, this "transparency of equipment" is dispelled, forcing a more deliberate mode of action. Leont'ev's development of breakdown hinges on the analytic distinction he made among Activities, Actions, and Operations. When the necessary conditions for an Operation are absent, the chain of Operations becomes transformed ("unfolded") back into a sequence of independent Actions. Dewey's notion of breakdown is related to his views on sensory excitation, stimulus and response, and the habit-formation function in the lives of complex organisms. Implications of these three models for learning and instruction are developed.

Thus we often learn more by our mistakes rather than by rote. We learn by reassembling that which we erred in. In a similar vein being-in-the world is also a noun a verb. On the one hand it may mean an individual, or being, modified by “in-the-world” or it may be the action of being, the gerund of to be, “in-the-world”. Ironically reading and interpreting Heidegger is itself filed with such noun type breakdowns and needs to reassemble them. Perhaps it is the German mannerism. Heidegger, even in his later years, after having been exposed to the evils of the Nazis, did not learn by breakdown, in fact he continued to try to justify his actions. In a similar manner Eichmann tried not to correct the past evils but to reconstruct them to his own ends. Arendt, thus trained by Heidegger in the world of Dasein, breakdown, semiotics, seems to have missed the very drama before her in Jerusalem. Thus the value of Stangneth’s work is the opening up of the process, deconstructing the text, and laying bare the players.

[1] Stangneth, B., Eichmann Before Jerusalem: The Unexamined Life of a Mass Murderer, Knopf (New York) 2014.

[3] One could examine the Farias book, Heidegger and Nazism, Temple Univ Press, 1989, to get what may be a critical but detailed overview, limited somewhat by the time of its writing because of the still closed access to closed East German archives. A subsequent book by Ott, Martin Heidegger, A political Life, Basic (New York) 1993, which provides a similar but less polemic a presentation of Heidegger and the Nazis.

[4] Ettinger, E., Hannah Arendt Martin Heidegger, Yale Press (New Haven) 1995.

[7] Honan, NY Times, Nov 5, 1996, p 25.

[8] Winograd, T., F. Flores, Understanding Computers and Cognition, Addison Wesley (Reading MA), 1987. My old copy, I have a second, is marked page by page recording each time I went through it. As a result I went and taught the first course at MIT on Multimedia Communications (Fall 1989), influenced by this short treatise. The question I was trying to address at the time was: how would people communicate as we moved into a distributed multimedia environment? The semiotics of communicating was at that time becoming the challenge. In a sense Winograd and Flores saw that through the lens of Heidegger.

[9] Scrunton, R., A Short History of Modern Philosophy, Routledge (New York) 2002. pp 270-280. In fact Scrunton states: “It is impossible to summarize Heidegger’s work, which no one has claimed to understand completely.”

[10] See on p 31

[11] Timothy Koschmann, Kari Kuutti & Larry Hickman, The Concept of Breakdown in Heidegger, Leont'ev, and Dewey and Its Implications for Education, Mind, Culture, and Activity, Volume 5, Issue 1, 1998 pages 25-41