Sunday, March 31, 2019

Rights, and their Loss



A letter from Thomas Paine to Thomas Jefferson, [1]:we have the following

AFTER I got home, being alone and wanting amusement I sat down to explain to myself (for there is such a thing) my Ideas of natural and civil rights and the distinction between them— I send them to you to see how nearly we agree.

Thus there was and still remains a distinction. Herein Paine describes Natural Rights, those stated expressly in part in the Bill of Rights, and enshrined in the Constitution. Yet which of the Rights in the Bill of Rights are Natural or civil?

Suppose 20 persons, strangers to each other, to meet in a country not before inhabited. Each would be a Sovereign in his own natural right.

Now this pre-dates Rawls and in a sense exceeds the complexity of Rawls and the development of the inhibiting construct of Social Justice.

His will would be his Law, but his power, in many cases, inadequate to his right, and the consequence would be that each might be exposed, not only to each other, but to the other nineteen. It would then occur to them that their condition would be much improved, if a way could be devised to exchange that quantity of danger into so much protection, so that each individual should possess the strength of the whole number.

Note, Paine comes back to the singular entity of the individual, the basis of any and all Natural Rights.

As all their rights, in the first case, are natural rights, and the exercise of those rights supposed only by their own natural individual power, they would begin by distinguishing between those rights they could individually exercise fully and perfectly and those they could not.

Here he comes and reflects on the Natural Rights and what limits if any could be imposed as a result of entering into some form of compact. I would argue that in Rawls discussion, the assembly is formed by individuals without any rights, Natural or Civil, and in such a de novo situation the outcome is skewed. However Paine foresaw the problem that Rawls was blind to, namely the inherent rights of the individual, the Natural Rights.

Of the first kind are the rights of thinking, speaking, forming and giving opinions, and perhaps all those which can be fully exercised by the individual without the aid of exterior assistance— or in other words, rights of personal competency.—

Here Paine attempts to law forth the Natural Rights. These rights were well understood by 18th Century people, they were the basis for our own Bill of Rights.

Of the second kind are those of personal protection, or acquiring and possessing property, in the exercise of which the individual natural power is less than the natural right.

It is interesting to see Paine place property rights as being a lesser than a Natural Right. For it was in the writings of Ockham that we first see individual rights and amongst them the right to property. The right to own, to use, to transfer property, a right resulting from the work of the individual and a construct handed down to Locke. As for personal protection, one would assume self defense is a prime Natural Right, it is a corollary of self-defense, of self-survival.

Having drawn this line they agree to retain individually the first Class of Rights, or those of personal competency; and so detach from their personal possession the second class, or those of defective power and to accept in lieu thereof a right to the whole power produced by a condensation of all the parts. These I conceive to be civil rights or rights of Compact, and are distinguishable from Natural rights, because in the one we act wholly in our own person, in the other we agree not to do so, but act under the guarantee of society.

Rights of Compact or civil rights are those which we as a society would agree to assert and enforce. The Natural Right as Paine asserts is the right to act in one's own person. Then is not self-preservation such a right? For Paine perhaps not because it asserts an act upon another. What os the Natural Right of Free Speech, again Paine may argue it impacts another. Paradoxically many of what we assert are Natural act upon another. Why do we need a guarantee of society to worship as we so choose, to have property, to speak, to have a free press?

It therefore follows that the more of those imperfect natural rights, or rights of imperfect power we give up and thus exchange the more security we possess, and as the word liberty is often mistakenly put for security Mr. Wilson has confused his argument by confounding his terms.

Here is the essence, the battle between liberty and security.

But it does not follow that the more natural rights of every kind we resign the more security we possess, because if we resign those of the first class we may suffer much by the exchange, for where the right and the power are equal with each other in the individual naturally they ought to rest there.

The statement is quite powerful. If we give up our natural rights we do not gain security! The individual suffers. We must assert and sustain our natural rights, and the security that is sought is done so only at the peril of the mob. Those who assert that society as a whole can be more secure, say in health care or environmental concerns, do so at the diminution of the primal individual or Natural Rights. As Paine notes they do so at their peril.

Mr. Wilson must have some allusion to this Distinction or his position would be subject to the inference you draw from it. I consider the individual sovereignty of the states retained under the Act of Confederation to be the second Class of rights. It becomes dangerous because it is defective in the power necessary to support it. It answers the pride and purpose of a few men in each state— but the State collectively is injured by it.

Where Paine failed in regards to the French Revolution was understanding the power of the mob, of Robespierre and of Danton, of the many who used the Revolution to assert their power. One need just look back to the 14th Century in France and England and the mobs in both. In France it was the Jacquerie who roamed about slaughtering at will, the power of the mob, while in 1381 we have the Peasants Revolt in England the confronting of the King. Chaucer may have been fearful but not the King. The result was no slaughtering but the evolution of the law.

By the time of the 18th Century we again see the brutality of the French Revolution as compared to the rather "gentler" American Revolution. The French tend to show the impact of the mob. That should be a warning for any who seek the libertine stands of the Social Justice warriors.


[1] Paine, Thomas; Mark Philp. Rights of Man, Common Sense, and Other Political Writings (Oxford World's Classics) (Kindle Locations 1615-1622). OUP Oxford. Kindle Edition.